Three (3) Moral Guidance on Prioritizing Care During a Pandemic(or how to resist the temptation during this time of Pandemic & all time, to devalue human life, specially of the most vulnerable in our society)

As our society struggles to come to terms with the COVID-19 pandemic, for which our resources to treat the ill may well prove inadequate, difficult, and heart-wrenching decisions may have to be made by physicians and nurses.

In a Christian society like ours, we owe them as much guidance as possible, and we should want that guidance to be framed in ways that protect our society—and each of us individually—from temptations that will come all too readily to mind.

In cases where decisions must be made about who shall be saved, when not all can be saved, we also decide what sort of society we want ours to be—we are constituting ourselves as a certain kind of people.

When faced with scarcity, some will be tempted simply to pass by those who are older, the physically disabled or cognitively impaired, those who seem to have little to contribute to our common life.

Indeed, some of the proposals for treatment allocation that have been made in different Western societies may already reflect a yielding to that temptation.

We believe that such approaches are unacceptable, and recent statements by the Holy Father on discrimination against the elderly or the disabled support this judgment.

But there are additional ways in which even otherwise upright decisions could bring with them misinterpretations, seductions, and temptations that it would be wrong to accept

Here, we identify three temptations in particular, along with principles to counter these, that we believe must be avoided when issuing, following, or contemplating guidelines for allocating resources in this time of scarcity.

Various guidelines have been proposed, including, prominently, those by Ezekiel Emanuel and his distinguished co-authors that appeared in the New England Journal of Medicine.

Helpful as these are in several respects, we believe it is also important to consider some social pathologies to which our current situation might contribute.

I.  Allowed casualties are not intentional killings.

A first temptation will be to see the deaths allowed in consequence of our decision to treat some and not others as intentional killings.

Decisions to save some may be framed as decisions to kill others. And this slippage is likely to be encouraged by critics as well as friends of our rationing decisions.

But the slippage must be resisted. Already, attacks on the distinction between killing and accepting death as a foreseen side effect of an otherwise morally legitimate act whose object is not death itself, are staples of the pro-euthanasia and physician-assisted-suicide movement.

If withdrawing a ventilator from one close to death is permitted, they ask, why not intentionally kill the same person in order to eliminate his suffering? After all, both, it is alleged, are “intentional” taking of life.

The answer is that intentional killing is not the same as allowing a person to die as a proportionate side effect of an otherwise sound moral choice.

In intentional killing, someone’s death is deliberately caused either as an end (out of hatred, for example) or as a means to something else (such as the relief of suffering).

But when burdensome treatments are refused or withdrawn precisely to avoid the burdens they impose, the intention is to avoid those burdens, and death, even if foreseen, is not intended as a means or as an end, but is accepted only as a side effect.

IT IS THE TREATMENT THAT IS BURDENSOME, NOT THE PATIENT.

Similarly, decisions to save some are not choices to kill others, as some authors acknowledge.

This must be held steady in the mind’s eye, lest our allocation choices be used as cover to advance the regime of physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia.

Accordingly we need to exercise tremendous caution in our language: “choosing who will live and who will die” is a dangerous way of expressing what we are about in trying to save whom we can, while mourning the loss of those we are unable to save.

II.  Human lives are all of equal value.

Allocation decisions that will be made in our crisis will, again, have lethal effects in certain cases. When not all can be saved, some will perish. The NEJM guidelines mentioned above make some important recommendations for who should be given priority of treatment.

Surely it is right to say, as they do, that critical COVID-19 interventions—testing, PPE, ICU beds, ventilators, therapeutics, and vaccines—should go first to front-line health care workers and others who care for ill patients and who keep critical infrastructure operating, particularly workers who face a high risk of infection and whose training makes them difficult to replace.

But no such prioritization principles should be allowed to undermine a core conviction of our moral tradition, viz., that the lives of all human beings are of inherent, equal, and indeed incalculable value.

⁃ It is a constant temptation of humanity to elevate the lives of some over the lives of others, and this will surely be augmented by the practice of prioritization.

But it should be clear that, while there are valid reasons (in certain circumstances) to give priority to, for example, health care workers, this hardly means that their lives are more valuable, or more important, than the lives of their patients.

We must be vigilant to ensure that the coronavirus crisis not lead to any cheapening of the value and dignity of each individual human being’s life.

This must especially be kept in mind in thinking about health care allocation for the elderly and disabled once this pandemic has passed. The elderly are not owed less because of their age; nor are the disabled to be given a lesser share of the healthcare resources to which all are entitled.

We need to emerge from the pandemic with these principles intact.

III.  Expressive significance matters.

And this leads to our third point. Consider the language used by the authors of the NEJM piece:

“Maximization of benefits can be understood as saving the most individual lives or as saving the most life-years by giving priority to patients likely to survive longest after treatment.”

The concern that a life-years approach, even if used only as a secondary consideration, could come to be understood in ways that would cut against the claims of the elderly, the disabled, and those who seem to have little to contribute.

Simply put, we fear the practical effects of emphasizing life-years, specially in a society that “worship” youth and the natural effects of age are despised, in practice such a policy could appear to systematically privilege the lives of the young over the old.

It may happen, but God forbid, that across the country, and with the whole nation watching, the pattern would recur: a ventilator would be denied to an older patient and given to a younger one; denied to the 50-year-old in favor of the 30-year-old or the 15-year-old; taken from the middle-aged or retired, from parents and grandparents.

What lesson would people draw from this, and what attitudes might it entrench? That depends in part on what our culture has already primed us to think.

Sometimes we fall into a pattern of thinking of the elderly as a “burden”—on themselves and on us. We already have political movements, and in some Western societies, laws and policies, that would permit or encourage assisted suicide or euthanasia for those with lives judged to be no longer “worth living” or “burdensome” to society, including the frail elderly.

In this milieu, a policy of almost always prioritizing the young over the old could reflect and entrench a bigotry that is already widespread. It could lead to a further

devaluation of the lives of the elderly, which could work severe and often lethal harms far beyond the triage scenarios imposed by public health emergencies.

That is a possibility that gives us strong prudential reasons to: oppose any principles that would advise doctors to maximize the number of life-years saved rather than to look to the number of lives saved—old or young.

IV. Conclusion.

Moving forward, we must not blur the distinction between “saving the most individual lives” and “saving the most life-years.”

A patient who—even if successfully treated—is likely to live only a few more years is, here and now, equal in dignity to one who may live for decades if successfully treated.

Therefore, we should focus on the benefits of treatment during this pandemic by prioritizing those with the most profound needs and those who are most likely to survive the treatment.

Rather than claim to maximize benefits by attempting to calculate the number of “life-years” we can maximize, we should focus on the on the:

“patient’s objective clinical state, as best it can be assessed, for example by using a clinical scoring system to determine who has the best chance at survival.”

Doing so will almost surely still leave us uneasy and discontented, because we cannot do all the good we would like to accomplish. But we will not risk contributing to a cultural tendency to undermine our understanding of the equal worth of the elderly and disabled.

This is a reasonable way forward in our decision-making that affects all those—young and old, able-bodied and disabled—whom we are committed to regarding as our equals.

None of this is to deny, however, that in a time of pandemic, such as this, there might be occasions when some patients should themselves consider—not out of legal or even strict moral duty, but rather as an act of generosity—giving up access to something to which they are entitled so that someone else might have it.

None of us should place greater value on one life than we place on another, but any of us may rightly decide for ourselves that we will live in such a way that we are prepared forgo care in order that someone else may live.

In the next few weeks, as the pandemic perhaps reaches its zenith, we will have the opportunity to decide once again what sort of society we intend to be. We should eschew all invidious discrimination and recommit ourselves to treating all who are ill as bearers of profound, inherent, and equal worth and dignity.

————————

Lastly, this is not part of the guidelines but just some thought.

We also have a responsibility to be prepared ethically for the next pandemic. Every nation probably needs a national bioethics commission. Not having one seems ill-advised. Our contemporary world is saturated with bioethical issues. But commissions function slowly and deliberatively. It is also too late for a bioethics commission to help us now, but just as we need to prepare medically, socially and economically for the next pandemic, so we need to prepare ethically.

———————-

*Source Links:

*Moral Guidance on Prioritizing Care During a Pandemic – Public Discourse = A Joint Statement

*Respirators, our rights, right and wrong: Medical ethics in an age of coronavirus – New York Daily News

—————————————

⁃ A Blessed and very meaningful Easter to all of us.

⁃ May we find meaning in all the sufferings, hardships, and pain we see in our midst everyday, and take courage from the Risen Lord!

⁃ Let us find ways to be of service to others, to find ways TO BE EXCELLENT WITH EACH OTHER

🙂❤️✝️

JOSEPH A. CORDERO, MD, FPCS, FPALES, FPSGS

Husband and Father

General Surgery; Minimally Invasive Surgery and Surgical Endoscopy; Breast and Soft Tissue Surgical Oncology; Surgical Education and Training; Medical Ethics and Bioethics

Published by josephcorderomd

JOSEPH A. CORDERO B.Sc.(Psych), M.D., F.P.S.G.S., F.P.A.L.E.S., F.P.C.S. LOVING HUSBAND & FATHER General Surgery; Minimally Invasive Surgery and Surgical Endoscopy; Breast and Soft Tissue Surgical Oncology; Surgical Education and Training; Medical Ethics and Bioethics

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

Create your website at WordPress.com
Get started
%d bloggers like this: